The Tribune - Spectrum

ART & LITERATURE
'ART AND SOUL
BOOKS
MUSINGS
TIME OFF
YOUR OPTION
ENTERTAINMENT
BOLLYWOOD BHELPURI
TELEVISION
WIDE ANGLE
FITNESS
GARDEN LIFE
NATURE
SUGAR 'N' SPICE
CONSUMER ALERT
TRAVEL
INTERACTIVE FEATURES
CAPTION CONTEST
FEEDBACK

Sunday, February 23, 2003
Books

Indian philosophy in one palatable gulp
Vijay Tankha

Classical Indian Philosophy
by J.N. Mohanty. Oxford. Pages 180. Rs 425.

AT last, a modern Indian philosopher straddling both the Western and Indian philosophical traditions has written an introduction to Indian philosophy. This is a long overdue book and we owe a debt to Bina Gupta for having badgered J. N. Mohanty to write it. The result is a work that is informed as well as informative, explicative as well as critical, clearly written as well as philosophically rigorous. Mohanty reviews the principal concerns of ancient and medieval Indian philosophy without either apology or adulation. If the book is to be faulted it is for brevity, a virtue that only sutrakaras ever took seriously.

Mohanty is known for his work in both western and Indian philosophy. He brings, thus, to the study of the Indian schools an ability to state their central problems in a vocabulary accessible to readers not conversant with classical Sanskrit as well the specialised philosophical vocabulary of each of the numerous schools. Such readers, a class to which most belong, are usually lost in a maze of technical terminology and unable to even approach the fundamental problems these schools were concerned with. As elsewhere, the nature of philosophical problems lies not in their abstruseness or complexity, but often in their excessive simplicity. Philosophers are those who see difficulties where nobody else ever thought there were any. At the core of philosophical systems and schools are, more often than not, rather simple problems. These are the ones that are the most intractable.

 


Mohanty, perhaps for this reason, departs from the usual practice that other writers of introductory works follow: employing a chronology that is part historical and part Vedantic in its overall assumptions. The schools of Indian philosophy (usually limited to six) are studied as if their doctrines were a progression from materialism to idealism, from heterodoxy to orthodoxy, a progressive move from the Upanishads, through Samkya and Nyaya to the culminating truths of Advaita Vedanta. Such an approach, even if not consciously articulated, lies behind many such readings of the history of Indian philosophy. There is, however, no easy alternative: if schools are to be dealt with sequentially, then, even if unintended, there is an appearance of progression where there are really a series of texts and commentaries complementing and contradicting each other. It is the appearance of unity, if anything, that is illusory.

Mohanty’s approach is to look across schools at the sorts of debates that different darsanas engaged in. He divides the broad area of their philosophical discourse into five subsets: epistemology, metaphysics, politics, law and morality, religion and art, and the realm of mysticism which he locates "beyond the subject object distinction." Within these regions, none of which is wholly independent of any other, Mohanty addresses some of the persistent concerns around which texts were written and debates conducted. Four questions that Mohanty identifies in the sphere of theory of knowledge, or Pramana Sastra, for instance, are all about the nature of consciousness: What is consciousness? Can it cognise itself? Is it intentional? In 27 pages, Mohanty provides an excellent introduction to the main theories of knowledge, discussing key doctrines in an engaging and illuminating way. It is interesting that the kind of knowledge that philosophers busied themselves with was knowledge of consciousness, the self, mind, or the cognition of the act of knowing itself. These of course were not the only possible objects of knowledge, nor were they always thought to be identical. Other ‘objects’ of knowledge included material objects, time, space, the relations between them, universals, God, all rubbing shoulders in a whole range of theories.

Many of these schools were robustly realist, but even they were not averse to considering the nature of subjective consciousness or selfhood. To counter their realist assumptions, idealist Buddhist schools offered an alternative minimalist ontology. Both viewed language as consistent with their concerns. Thus it would seem that the appeal to ordinary language was a means of vindicating theory long before it was thought up at Oxford. Nor were these opposed doctrines static, and it is to Mohanty’s credit that he gives us, in so brief an account, some sense of the historical time in which these complex doctrines evolved.

One of the most illuminating sections is the one on law, politics and morality: areas in which the traditional schools have long thought to be the most deficient. Mohanty here sets the record straight. It is just not the case that Indian philosophers did not engage in moral thinking (though it seems to be true that they did not think of it as a problem), it is just that they did not engage in the foundational exercise that characterises the thinking of philosophers such as Kant or Mill.

A short review like this cannot do justice to the wealth of insight and information that Mohanty brings to this subject. The best feature of this book is that it goes straight into the central questions of philosophy, which it addresses with a rigour that is rarely found in discussions of the Indian schools.

If there are lacunae in Mohanty’s presentation they are more likely to be the result of his aim: to provide an intellectually rich introduction to the principal (not by any means all) schools of Indian philosophy, forming a tradition that, we believe, stretches from at least the sixth century BC to the book here reviewed.